Specifically, the opposition to the updated definition of ‘mental health’ emerges from the broadened qualifications for receiving a diagnosis, including the generous accommodation for cultural deviation. As a result, the likelihood of being diagnosed with a mental illness increases by a vast margin. For example, research conducted by Richard Warner, a philosophy professor, verified “that there are many cases of behavior that Western psychiatry would classify as symptomatic of mental disorder, which are not seen within their own cultures as signs of mental illness” (cited in Perring). Permitting a margin of leeway in diagnosing mental disorders by using a loose framework, rather than precise criteria, establishes global inconsistency. To the greatest extreme, the DSM-IV’s definition is in contradiction with itself, therefore imploding its logic and demolishing its purpose as a reliable, shared standard for professionals in diagnosing a patient with a mental disorder. Consider, for example, a young man living in the United States who, under the cultural patterns in this country, does not have a mental disorder. However, if he were to move to India, clinicians would consider a different set of cultural norms, and there the young man may be diagnosed with a mental disorder. The DSM-IV’s definition of ‘mental disorder’ is therefore inadequate because it demolishes psychiatric reliability cross-culturally. The objection against the psychiatric adequacy of DSM-IV’s definition of ‘mental disorder’ succeeds because it establishes distrust in a diagnosis through permitting deviations from the core definition. For example, an individual could be restricted from a necessary treatment
Specifically, the opposition to the updated definition of ‘mental health’ emerges from the broadened qualifications for receiving a diagnosis, including the generous accommodation for cultural deviation. As a result, the likelihood of being diagnosed with a mental illness increases by a vast margin. For example, research conducted by Richard Warner, a philosophy professor, verified “that there are many cases of behavior that Western psychiatry would classify as symptomatic of mental disorder, which are not seen within their own cultures as signs of mental illness” (cited in Perring). Permitting a margin of leeway in diagnosing mental disorders by using a loose framework, rather than precise criteria, establishes global inconsistency. To the greatest extreme, the DSM-IV’s definition is in contradiction with itself, therefore imploding its logic and demolishing its purpose as a reliable, shared standard for professionals in diagnosing a patient with a mental disorder. Consider, for example, a young man living in the United States who, under the cultural patterns in this country, does not have a mental disorder. However, if he were to move to India, clinicians would consider a different set of cultural norms, and there the young man may be diagnosed with a mental disorder. The DSM-IV’s definition of ‘mental disorder’ is therefore inadequate because it demolishes psychiatric reliability cross-culturally. The objection against the psychiatric adequacy of DSM-IV’s definition of ‘mental disorder’ succeeds because it establishes distrust in a diagnosis through permitting deviations from the core definition. For example, an individual could be restricted from a necessary treatment